Kleene's recursion theorem

Kleene's recursion theorem Not to be confused with Kleene's theorem for regular languages.

In computability theory, Kleene's recursion theorems are a pair of fundamental results about the application of computable functions to their own descriptions. The theorems were first proved by Stephen Kleene in 1938[1] and appear in his 1952 book Introduction to Metamathematics.[2] A related theorem, which constructs fixed points of a computable function, is known as Rogers's theorem and is due to Hartley Rogers, Jr.[3] The recursion theorems can be applied to construct fixed points of certain operations on computable functions, to generate quines, and to construct functions defined via recursive definitions.

Contenu 1 Notation 2 Rogers's fixed-point theorem 2.1 Proof of the fixed-point theorem 2.2 Fixed-point-free functions 3 Kleene's second recursion theorem 3.1 Comparison to Rogers's theorem 3.2 Application to quines 3.3 Application to elimination of recursion 3.4 Reflexive programming 4 The first recursion theorem 4.1 Exemple 4.2 Proof sketch for the first recursion theorem 4.3 Comparison to the second recursion theorem 5 Generalized theorem 6 Voir également 7 Références 8 Lectures complémentaires 9 External links Notation The statement of the theorems refers to an admissible numbering {style d'affichage varphi } of the partial recursive functions, such that the function corresponding to index {style d'affichage e} est {style d'affichage varphi _{e}} .

Si {style d'affichage F} et {style d'affichage G} are partial functions on the natural numbers, the notation {displaystyle Fsimeq G} indicates that, for each n, Soit {style d'affichage F(n)} et {style d'affichage G(n)} are both defined and are equal, or else {style d'affichage F(n)} et {style d'affichage G(n)} are both undefined.

Rogers's fixed-point theorem Given a function {style d'affichage F} , a fixed point of {style d'affichage F} is an index {style d'affichage e} tel que {style d'affichage varphi _{e}simeq varphi _{F(e)}} . Rogers describes the following result as "a simpler version" of Kleene's (deuxième) recursion theorem.[4] Rogers's fixed-point theorem. Si {style d'affichage F} is a total computable function, it has a fixed point. Proof of the fixed-point theorem The proof uses a particular total computable function {style d'affichage h} , defined as follows. Given a natural number {style d'affichage x} , the function {style d'affichage h} outputs the index of the partial computable function that performs the following computation: Given an input {style d'affichage y} , first attempt to compute {style d'affichage varphi _{X}(X)} . If that computation returns an output {style d'affichage e} , then compute {style d'affichage varphi _{e}(y)} and return its value, si seulement.

Ainsi, for all indices {style d'affichage x} of partial computable functions, si {style d'affichage varphi _{X}(X)} est défini, alors {style d'affichage varphi _{h(X)}simeq varphi _{varphi _{X}(X)}} . Si {style d'affichage varphi _{X}(X)} is not defined, alors {style d'affichage varphi _{h(X)}} is a function that is nowhere defined. La fonction {style d'affichage h} can be constructed from the partial computable function {style d'affichage g(X,y)} described above and the s-m-n theorem: pour chaque {style d'affichage x} , {style d'affichage h(X)} is the index of a program which computes the function {displaystyle ymapsto g(X,y)} .

To complete the proof, laisser {style d'affichage F} be any total computable function, and construct {style d'affichage h} comme ci-dessus. Laisser {style d'affichage e} be an index of the composition {displaystyle Fcirc h} , which is a total computable function. Alors {style d'affichage varphi _{h(e)}simeq varphi _{varphi _{e}(e)}} by the definition of {style d'affichage h} . Mais, car {style d'affichage e} is an index of {displaystyle Fcirc h} , {style d'affichage varphi _{e}(e)=(Fcirc h)(e)} , Et ainsi {style d'affichage varphi _{varphi _{e}(e)}simeq varphi _{F(h(e))}} . By the transitivity of {style d'affichage simeq } , ça signifie {style d'affichage varphi _{h(e)}simeq varphi _{F(h(e))}} . Ainsi {style d'affichage varphi _{n}simeq varphi _{F(n)}} pour {displaystyle n=h(e)} .

This proof is a construction of a partial recursive function which implements the Y combinator.

Fixed-point-free functions A function {style d'affichage F} tel que {style d'affichage varphi _{e}not simeq varphi _{F(e)}} pour tous {style d'affichage e} is called fixed-point free. The fixed-point theorem shows that no total computable function is fixed-point free, but there are many non-computable fixed-point-free functions. Arslanov's completeness criterion states that the only recursively enumerable Turing degree that computes a fixed-point-free function is 0′, the degree of the halting problem.[5] Kleene's second recursion theorem The second recursion theorem is a generalization of Rogers's theorem with a second input in the function. One informal interpretation of the second recursion theorem is that it is possible to construct self-referential programs; voir "Application to quines" dessous.

The second recursion theorem. For any partial recursive function {style d'affichage Q(X,y)} there is an index {style d'affichage p} tel que {style d'affichage varphi _{p}simeq lambda y.Q(p,y)} .

The theorem can be proved from Rogers's theorem by letting {style d'affichage F(p)} be a function such that {style d'affichage varphi _{F(p)}(y)= Q(p,y)} (a construction described by the S-m-n theorem). One can then verify that a fixed-point of this {style d'affichage F} is an index {style d'affichage p} comme demandé. The theorem is constructive in the sense that a fixed computable function maps an index for Q into the index p.

Comparison to Rogers's theorem Kleene's second recursion theorem and Rogers's theorem can both be proved, rather simply, from each other.[6] Cependant, a direct proof of Kleene's theorem[7] does not make use of a universal program, which means that the theorem holds for certain subrecursive programming systems that do not have a universal program.

Application to quines A classic example using the second recursion theorem is the function {style d'affichage Q(X,y)=x} . The corresponding index {style d'affichage p} in this case yields a computable function that outputs its own index when applied to any value.[8] When expressed as computer programs, such indices are known as quines.

The following example in Lisp illustrates how the {style d'affichage p} in the corollary can be effectively produced from the function {style d'affichage Q} . The function s11 in the code is the function of that name produced by the S-m-n theorem.

Q can be changed to any two-argument function.

(setq Q '(lambda (xy) X)) (setq s11 '(lambda (f x) (list 'lambda '(y) (list f x 'y)))) (setq n (list 'lambda '(xy) (list Q (list s11 'x 'x) 'y))) (setq p (eval (list s11 n n))) The results of the following expressions should be the same. {style d'affichage varphi } p(nil) (eval (list p nil)) Q(p, nil) (eval (list Q p nil)) Application to elimination of recursion Suppose that {style d'affichage g} et {style d'affichage h} are total computable functions that are used in a recursive definition for a function {style d'affichage f} : {style d'affichage f(0,y)simeq g(y),} {style d'affichage f(x+1,y)simeq h(F(X,y),X,y),} The second recursion theorem can be used to show that such equations define a computable function, where the notion of computability does not have to allow, prima facie, for recursive definitions (par exemple, it may be defined by μ-recursion, or by Turing machines). This recursive definition can be converted into a computable function {style d'affichage varphi _{F}(e,X,y)} that assumes {style d'affichage e} is an index to itself, to simulate recursion: {style d'affichage varphi _{F}(e,0,y)simeq g(y),} {style d'affichage varphi _{F}(e,x+1,y)simeq h(varphi _{e}(X,y),X,y).} The recursion theorem establishes the existence of a computable function {style d'affichage varphi _{F}} tel que {style d'affichage varphi _{F}(X,y)simeq varphi _{F}(F,X,y)} . Ainsi {style d'affichage f} satisfies the given recursive definition.

Reflexive programming Reflexive, or reflective, programming refers to the usage of self-reference in programs. Jones presents a view of the second recursion theorem based on a reflexive language.[9] It is shown that the reflexive language defined is not stronger than a language without reflection (because an interpreter for the reflexive language can be implemented without using reflection); alors, it is shown that the recursion theorem is almost trivial in the reflexive language.

The first recursion theorem While the second recursion theorem is about fixed points of computable functions, the first recursion theorem is related to fixed points determined by enumeration operators, which are a computable analogue of inductive definitions. An enumeration operator is a set of pairs (UN,n) where A is a (code for a) finite set of numbers and n is a single natural number. Souvent, n will be viewed as a code for an ordered pair of natural numbers, particularly when functions are defined via enumeration operators. Enumeration operators are of central importance in the study of enumeration reducibility.

Each enumeration operator Φ determines a function from sets of naturals to sets of naturals given by {style d'affichage Phi (X)={nmid exists Asubseteq X[(UN,n)in Phi ]}.} A recursive operator is an enumeration operator that, when given the graph of a partial recursive function, always returns the graph of a partial recursive function.

A fixed point of an enumeration operator Φ is a set F such that Φ(F) =F. The first enumeration theorem shows that fixed points can be effectively obtained if the enumeration operator itself is computable.

First recursion theorem. The following statements hold. For any computable enumeration operator Φ there is a recursively enumerable set F such that Φ(F) = F and F is the smallest set with this property. For any recursive operator Ψ there is a partial computable function φ such that Ψ(Phi) = φ and φ is the smallest partial computable function with this property. Example Like the second recursion theorem, the first recursion theorem can be used to obtain functions satisfying systems of recursion equations. To apply the first recursion theorem, the recursion equations must first be recast as a recursive operator.

Consider the recursion equations for the factorial function f: {style d'affichage f(0)=1} {style d'affichage f(n+1)=(n+1)cdot f(n)} The corresponding recursive operator Φ will have information that tells how to get to the next value of f from the previous value. Cependant, the recursive operator will actually define the graph of f. Première, Φ will contain the pair {style d'affichage (varnothing ,(0,1))} . This indicates that f(0) is unequivocally 1, and thus the pair (0,1) is in the graph of f.

Prochain, for each n and m, Φ will contain the pair {style d'affichage ({(n,m)},(n+1,(n+1)cdot m))} . This indicates that, if f(n) is m, then f(n + 1) est (n + 1)m, so that the pair (n + 1, (n + 1)m) is in the graph of f. Unlike the base case f(0) = 1, the recursive operator requires some information about f(n) before it defines a value of f(n + 1).

The first recursion theorem (en particulier, partie 1) states that there is a set F such that Φ(F) =F. The set F will consist entirely of ordered pairs of natural numbers, and will be the graph of the factorial function f, comme voulu.

The restriction to recursion equations that can be recast as recursive operators ensures that the recursion equations actually define a least fixed point. Par exemple, consider the set of recursion equations: {style d'affichage g(0)=1} {style d'affichage g(n+1)=1} {style d'affichage g(2n)=0} There is no function g satisfying these equations, because they imply g(2) = 1 and also imply g(2) = 0. Thus there is no fixed point g satisfying these recursion equations. It is possible to make an enumeration operator corresponding to these equations, but it will not be a recursive operator.

Proof sketch for the first recursion theorem The proof of part 1 of the first recursion theorem is obtained by iterating the enumeration operator Φ beginning with the empty set. Première, a sequence Fk is constructed, pour {displaystyle k=0,1,ldots } . Let F0 be the empty set. Proceeding inductively, for each k, let Fk + 1 être {style d'affichage F_{k}cup Phi (F_{k})} . Pour terminer, F is taken to be {displaystyle bigcup F_{k}} . The remainder of the proof consists of a verification that F is recursively enumerable and is the least fixed point of Φ. The sequence Fk used in this proof corresponds to the Kleene chain in the proof of the Kleene fixed-point theorem.

The second part of the first recursion theorem follows from the first part. The assumption that Φ is a recursive operator is used to show that the fixed point of Φ is the graph of a partial function. The key point is that if the fixed point F is not the graph of a function, then there is some k such that Fk is not the graph of a function.

Comparison to the second recursion theorem Compared to the second recursion theorem, the first recursion theorem produces a stronger conclusion but only when narrower hypotheses are satisfied. Rogers uses the term weak recursion theorem for the first recursion theorem and strong recursion theorem for the second recursion theorem.[3] One difference between the first and second recursion theorems is that the fixed points obtained by the first recursion theorem are guaranteed to be least fixed points, while those obtained from the second recursion theorem may not be least fixed points.

A second difference is that the first recursion theorem only applies to systems of equations that can be recast as recursive operators. This restriction is similar to the restriction to continuous operators in the Kleene fixed-point theorem of order theory. The second recursion theorem can be applied to any total recursive function.

Generalized theorem In the context of his theory of numberings, Ershov showed that Kleene's recursion theorem holds for any precomplete numbering.[10] A Gödel numbering is a precomplete numbering on the set of computable functions so the generalized theorem yields the Kleene recursion theorem as a special case.[11] Given a precomplete numbering {style d'affichage non } , then for any partial computable function {style d'affichage f} with two parameters there exists a total computable function {style d'affichage t} with one parameter such that {displaystyle forall nin mathbb {N} :nu circ f(n,t(n))=nu circ t(n).} See also Denotational semantics, where another least fixed point theorem is used for the same purpose as the first recursion theorem. Fixed-point combinators, which are used in lambda calculus for the same purpose as the first recursion theorem. Diagonal lemma a closely related result in mathematical logic References Ershov, Yuri L. (1999). "Part 4: Mathematics and Computability Theory. 14. Theory of numbering". In Griffor, Edouard R. (éd.). Handbook of Computability Theory. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Volume. 140. Amsterdam: Elsevier. pp. 473–503. ISBN 9780444898821. OCLC 162130533. Récupéré 6 Peut 2020. Jones, Neil D. (1997). Computability and complexity: From a Programming Perspective. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Presse du MIT. ISBN 9780262100649. OCLC 981293265. Kleene, Stephen C. (1952). Introduction to Metamathematics. Bibliotheca Mathematica. North-Holland Publishing. ISBN 9780720421033. OCLC 459805591. Récupéré 6 Peut 2020. Roger, Hartley (1967). Theory of recursive functions and effective computability. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Presse du MIT. ISBN 9780262680523. OCLC 933975989. Récupéré 6 Peut 2020.

Footnotes ^ Kleene, Stephen C. (1938). "On notation for ordinal numbers" (PDF). Journal of Symbolic Logic. 3 (4): 150–155. est ce que je:10.2307/2267778. ISSN 0022-4812. JSTOR 2267778. Récupéré 6 Peut 2020. ^ Kleene 1952. ^ Sauter à: a b Rogers 1967. ^ Rogers 1967, §11.2. ^ Soare, R.I. (1987). Recursively Enumerable Sets and Degrees: A Study of Computable Functions and Computably Generated Sets. Perspectives en logique mathématique. Berlin and New York City: Springer Verlag. p. 88. ISBN 9780387152998. OCLC 318368332. ^ Jones 1997, pp. 229–30. ^ Kleene 1952, pp. 352–3. ^ Cutland, Nigel J. (1980). Computability: An Introduction to Recursive Function Theory. la presse de l'Universite de Cambridge. p. 204. est ce que je:10.1017/cbo9781139171496. ISBN 9781139935609. OCLC 488175597. Récupéré 6 Peut 2020. ^ Jones 1997. ^ Barendregt, Henk; Terwijn, Sebastiaan A. (2019). "Fixed point theorems for precomplete numberings". Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 170 (10): 1151–1161. est ce que je:10.1016/j.apal.2019.04.013. hdl:2066/205967. ISSN 0168-0072. S2CID 52289429. Récupéré 6 Peut 2020. p. 1151. ^ See Ershov 1999, §4.14 for a survey in English. Further reading Jockusch, C. G.; Lerman, M; Soleil, R.I.; Solovay, R.M. (1989). "Recursively enumerable sets modulo iterated jumps and extensions of Arslanov's completeness criterion". Le Journal de la logique symbolique. 54 (4): 1288–1323. est ce que je:10.1017/S0022481200041104. ISSN 0022-4812. JSTOR 2274816. Liens externes "Recursive Functions" entry by Piergiorgio Odifreddi in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2012. Catégories: Computability theoryTheorems in the foundations of mathematics

Si vous voulez connaître d'autres articles similaires à Kleene's recursion theorem vous pouvez visiter la catégorie Computability theory.

Laisser un commentaire

Votre adresse email ne sera pas publiée.

Monter

Nous utilisons nos propres cookies et ceux de tiers pour améliorer l'expérience utilisateur Plus d'informations